Publications
This chapter models an approach to the phenomenological study of practitioners’ experiences of mindfulness meditation. I draw primarily upon Husserl and Fink’s phenomenological philosophy and the existential phenomenological method of qualitative research in psychology that originated at Duquesne University in the 1960’s. The mindfulness practice examined is that of “meditative remembrance” or silent dhikr originating in classical Sufism, as practiced within a contemporary, traditionally authorized Sufi lineage. This study examines dhikr as a distinct form of mindfulness meditation, exemplifying how phenomenology can explore the meanings of meditators’ narratives. In parallel I seek to convey the relevance of Husserl and Fink’s exploration of self and world-constitution for the study of meditation: in particular, phenomenology’s retracing of the generative flow of constituting consciousness which underlies-and is in a certain sense prior to-the personal ego.
Applebaum (2023) Dhikr as Mindfulness: Meditative Remembrance in Sufism. Journal of Humanistic Psychology
Mindfulness practices adapted from Theravada Buddhism have become widespread among many in Western societies who seek stress reduction and greater present-centeredness. Less well known is the mindfulness practice in Sufism–the mystical path of Islam–known as meditative remembrance (dhikr). While mindfulness is often understood as a self-help technique, the aim of Buddhist and Sufi meditative paths is not limited to enhancing the well-being of a self that is envisioned as strictly bounded. Rather, both meditative paths aim at unitive mystical experience, which is held to profoundly transform the meaning of the practitioner’s selfhood as such. Whereas Buddhism’s non-self doctrine is generally understood to hold that personal selfhood is an illusion, this is not the case for Akbari Sufism. This inquiry takes a phenomenological approach, exploring the varied meanings of being or “having” a self in the context of mindfulness, and contrasting these with the humanistic psychology of Abraham Maslow. I contrast Theravada and Akbari Sufism’s understandings of the aim of meditation and the meanings of selfhood and compares both traditions with Abraham Maslow’s view of self-transcendence.
Applebaum (2019) Remembrance: A Husserlian Phenomenology of Sufi Practice, Journal of Speculative Philosophy
The study seeks to answer the phenomenological question: what in essence is religious experience—specifically, the lived-experience of “remembrance” (dhikr) in Sufi practice within the schools of Sufism shaped by the “Greatest Master,” Ibn al-‘Arabi (1165-1240)? The eidetic structure of remembrance is proposed as: the awakening of the individuated human subject to recollecting the primordial ground of his or her identity as a dynamic instantiation of the Absolute. This is simultaneously experienced as the subject becoming the object of remembrance—that is, being remembered by the Absolute. This transforms the psychological ego’s relationship to her/his own embodied, affective, and cognitive living, as the “center of gravity” of that ego shifts from an egocentric one—that is, an identification with the natural attitude standpoint of the personal ego—to progressively greater centeredness in the transcendental ego as a locus of ongoing world-constitution and primordial self-presence, while nevertheless living as a unique individual.
Applebaum (2018) The I and the We: Psychological Reflections on Husserl’s Egology in Phenomenology and the Social Context of Psychiatry, M. Englander (Ed.)
This chapter seeks to answer the following question: How can a Husserlian phenomenology contribute to psychiatry’s understanding of and ability to work within the field of social interrelatedness–that which is lived by a we, not merely by an I? I begin with first-person description in an interpretive dialogue with Husserl’s writings on egology and its relationship to the “you” and thus the “we.” In explicating the data so given, I rely on both Husserl’s static and genetic phenomenology. I work with personal, experiential data because the data of phenomenological psychological research is intimate–and in seeking to bring Husserlian insights down into the soil and messiness of everyday psychological lived-experience, we work in a primary way with raw, first-person narratives. This chapter is not intended as a full-fledged psychological study; rather, it is intended to exemplify how data opens to the phenomenological eye. In this case the narrative material is my own, but the data might just as easily come from an Other–in any case, our lives are the flesh without which the eidos would be disembodied, lacking life and warmth. For psychological researchers, the embodied lived-experiences given to us in in the form of narratives are more than mere raw material for the scholarly ascription of essences–they are the human setting through which the eide are clarified in order to return to us, incarnate, pregnant with meaning for future living. This essay aims to contribute to illuminating a Husserlian sense of the “we” by exploring the layers of the “I” and its origins and embeddedness, for Husserl, in I-You relations–that is, within the we-world of companionship (socius) and community.
Yoshida (2015) Reconsideration on Living with Multiple Psychologies 十牛図 挿入済
YOSHIDA Akihiro writes: My motive to investigate the problem of Living with Multiple Psychologies has its origin in my own personal history of wondering in the chaotic world of multiple psychologies. Upon reflection, every time at the critical turning points in my life in the world of multiple psychologies, I was at a loss which new way to choose and decide to go further, and I eagerly wished to have good advices, if available, from any of my knowledgeable seniors, teachers and/or senior psychologists. However, I was not always able to get enlightening and encouraging advices. Now, as an old psychologist, who has my own personal experiences of wondering through multiple psychologies, I wish I could offer at least some helpful advices, —-which, when I was young, I had desired desperately in vain, —-to our younger generations who might be, consciously or unconsciously, now desperately wishing to have advices just as I was desiring years ago.
Applebaum (2014) Intentionality and Narrativity in Phenomenological Research Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology
Abstract: According to Husserl scholars such as Mohanty (1989) description and interpretation coexist within Husserl’s work and are envisioned as complementary rather than mutually exclusive approaches to inquiry. This essay argues that exploring the implications of this philosophical complementarity for psychological research would require distinguishing between the multiple meanings of “interpretation” and between differing modes of interpretation within qualitative data. Husserl’s model of passive and active intentionality and Ricoeur’s theory of narrativity are examined in order to explore their relevance for research. It is argued that interview data can demonstrate both actively and passively intended dimensions, and the psychological meaningfulness of this complexity points to the relevance of not only of Husserl’s static analysis but his genetic analysis as well. Likewise, it is argued that Ricoeur’s work on narrativity and narrative identity is invaluable in grasping ways in which narrative data is intrinsically self-interpretive, expresses self-identity, and is both situated within and responsive to the larger social horizon within which the interview is given.
Abstract: In this article, interviewing from a descriptive, phenomenological, human scientific perspective is examined. Methodological issues are raised in relation to evaluative criteria as well as reflective matters that concern the phenomenological researcher.The data collection issues covered are 1) the selection of participants, 2) the number of participants in a study, 3) the interviewer and the questions, and 4) data collection procedures.Certain conclusions were drawn indicating that phenomenological research methods cannot be evaluated on the basis of an empiricist theory of science, but must be critiqued from within a phenomenological theory of science. Some reflective matters, experienced by the phenomenological researcher, are also elaborated upon. -Published in the Journal of Phenomenological Psychology
Applebaum (2011) Beyond scientism and relativism-Amedeo Giorgi’s Commitment to Human Science
Abstract: This is my chapter in the festschrift volume celebrating Amedeo Giorgi’s career in phenomenological psychology. I pose the question, why should the scientific status of qualitative psychological researcher be a compelling issue for the next generation of scholars? I explore the criteria for science proposed by Giorgi, and discuss van Manen’s hermeneutic method as an alternate, aestheticizing approach.
Applebaum (2007) Considerazioni critiche sui metodi fenomenologici di Moustakas e di van Manen (Critical reflections on the phenomenological methods of Moustakas and van Manen)
Abstract: My objective in this paper is to reflect critically on Max van Manen’s Researching Lived Experience (1990) and Clark Moustakas’ Phenomenological Research Methods (1994) from the standpoint of Amedeo Giorgi’s phenomenological psychological method. Moustakas grasp of the central tenets of Husserl’s phenomenology is interrogated, including his representation of what the psychological and transcendental realms signify for Husserl’s phenomenology. Van Manen’s presentation is questioned as it appears to leave unclarified important differences between hermeneutic and descriptive phenomenology with the result being a variety of epistemological inconsistencies in the research approach as presented.
Broome (2011) Phenomenological Psychological Dissertation Method Chapter
Method Chapter: This document is the methodology chapter from Broomé’s 2011 doctoral dissertation outlining the Descriptive Phenomenological Psychological Method of research as taught by Amedeo P. Giorgi. Giorgi (2009) based his method on Husserl’s descriptive phenomenological philosophy as an alternative epistemology for human science research. This method section references Giorgi’s work and the phenomenological tradition of Husserl, Merleau-Ponty and others. Each step of Giorgi’s (2009) modified Husserlian method is described and explained in the context of doing psychological research on the lived-experience of the participants in the dissertation research. The steps are: (1) assume the phenomenological attitude, (2) read entire written account for a sense of the whole, (3) delineate meaning units, (4) transform the meaning units into psychologically sensitive statements of their lived-meanings, and (5) synthesize a general psychological structure of the experience base on the constituents of the experience. It is the first-person psychological perspective that is sought so that an empathetic position can be adopted by the end-user of the research.
Applebaum (2012) Phenomenological Psychological Research as Science
Abstract: Part of teaching the descriptive phenomenological psychological method is to assist students in grasping their previously unrecognized assumptions regarding the meaning of “science.” This paper is intended to address a variety of assumptions that are encountered when introducing students to the descriptive phenomenological psychological method pioneered by Giorgi. These assumptions are: 1) That the meaning of “science” is exhausted by empirical science, and therefore qualitative research, even if termed “human science,” is more akin to literature or art than methodical, scientific inquiry; 2) That as a primarily aesthetic, poetic enterprise human scientific psychology need not attempt to achieve a degree of rigor and epistemological clarity analogous (while not equivalent) to that pursued by natural scientists; 3) That “objectivity” is a concept belonging to natural science, and therefore human science ought not to strive for objectivity because this would require “objectivizing” the human being; 4) That qualitative research must always adopt an “interpretive” approach, description being seen as merely a mode of interpretation. These assumptions are responded to from a perspective drawing primarily upon Husserl and Merleau-Ponty, but also upon Eagleton’s analysis of aestheticism.
Broomé (2011) An Empathetic Psychological Perspective of Police Deadly Force Training
Abstract: Police officers must be able to make an accurate appraisal of a lethal encounter and respond with appropriate force to mitigate the threat to their own lives and to the lives of others. Contemporary police deadly force training places the cadet in mock lethal encounters, which are designed to simulate those occurring in the real lives of law enforcement officers. This Reality Base Training (RBT) is designed to provide cadets with experiences that require their reactions to be within the law, policies and procedures, and ethics while undergoing a very stressful, emotional, and physically dynamic situation (Artwohl & Christensen, 1997; Blum, 2000; Grossman, 1996; Miller, 2008; Murray, 2006). Three police cadets provided writ- ten accounts of their deadly force training experiences in the RBT format. The descriptive phenomenological psychological method was used to analyze the data and to synthesize a general psychological structure of their experiences. The results reveal the perceptions, thoughts, feelings and behaviors reflecting the role of con- sciousness and psychological subjectivity in the participants’ understandings and decision-making in the simulated situations. -Published in the Journal of Phenomenological Psychology
Applebaum (2011) Amedeo Giorgi and Psychology as a Human Science
Abstract: Over the course of the last fifty years Amedeo Giorgi has played a leading role in the movement to redirect psychological research from an imitation of the natural sciences toward a human science paradigm. He founded the first phenomenological psychological research program in the United Stated at Duquesne University, and continued his development of phenomenological psychology at Saybrook Graduate School. Giorgi’s descriptive phenomenological method is a rigorous approach to qualitative research that is founded in the philosophical phenomenology of Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. The descriptive phenomenological method makes use of the phenomenological epoché, reduction, imaginative variation, and search for essential psychological structures. Giorgi’s approach to conveying phenomenology embodies a wide-ranging and incisive critique of empirical psychology’s limitations, and seeks to establish scientific criteria appropriate for the study of lived, human subjectivity. -published in the journal NeuroQuantology
Abstract: Dans les premières pages d’Introduction à la phénoménologie, Patočka définit la phénoménologie comme « une réflexion parallèle sur le sens autant des choses que de la vie humaine » : réflexion qui nécessite une science rigoureuse, ainsi qu’une vision de la science dans sa « signification fondamentale pour la vie. » D’une telle manière Patočka accomplit un double geste : d’un côté, il formule d’une manière explicite son idée de la phénoménologie ; de l’autre, il pose les termes d’un questionnement tout à fait crucial concernant les rapports entre éthique et phénoménologie. Il s’agira notamment pour nous de ramener à la source ce questionnement implicitement formulé par Patočka. La science phénoménologique est-elle compréhensible sans le support de l’éthique ? –published in the journal Etudes Phénoménologiques
Abstract: Within the Husserlian phenomenological philosophical tradition, description and interpretation coexist. Teaching the practice of phenomenological psychological research, however, requires careful articulation of the differences between a descriptive and an interpretive relationship to what is given in qualitative data. If as researchers we neglect the epistemological foundations of our work, or avoid working through difficult methodological issues, our work invites dismissal as inadequate science, undermining the effort to strongly establish psychology along qualitative lines. The first article in this two-part discussion is a Husserlian investigation of the meaning of “method” for psychology as a human science. This investigation is undertaken in the light of some researchers’ appropriations of Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneutics in the service of non-methodical praxes. The second article will address some implications of the attempt to structure qualitative psychological research along “Gadamerian” lines, taking seriously the references to Gadamer’s work made by researchers such as van Manen and Smith. -published in The Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology
Applebaum (2010) Ricerca psicologica fenomenlogica come scienza
Abstract: Husserl formula le sue ricerche fenomenologiche come risposta al momento storico in cui vive(va), un periodo di crisi di civiltà in cui “lo scetticismo–sosteneva–si stava diffondendo, minacciando in generale di screditare il grande progetto di una scienza rigorosa”. Per Husserl (1970) questo scetticismo rappresentava un collasso della fede nella “ragione”, intesa allo stesso modo in cui gli antichi opponevano l’episteme alla doxa: ad essere in gioco, per Husserl, era la fiducia della società nella capacita degli esseri umani di dare significato alla vita individuale e pubblica attraverso il ragionamento (p. 13). La fenomenologia era destinata a combattere la dilagante visione secondo la quale “la ragione non ha più niente da dire rispetto alle scottanti questioni sudi chi e che cosa siamo” (Dodd, 2004, p. 47). Quello di Husserl fu un tentativo di ridare vita all’originale significato di “scienza”, che sosteneva essere stato ampiamente dimenticato o oscurato dalle scienze naturali. Quasi un secolo dopo, i seguaci dell’approccio husserliano alla ricerca psicologica fenomenologica iniziata da Amedeo Giorgi (1970, 2009) incontrano una difficoltà simile. Lavorando con gli studenti ci si imbatte spesso in un atteggiamento di scetticismo, espresso in affermazioni come “tutta la conoscenza é interpretazione”, oppure ogni pretesa di verità riguardo a dei dati é “solo la tua interpretazione”; o ancora, l’affermazione che nella ricerca qualitativa “non esiste qualcosa come la conoscenza oggettiva” perché “stiamo studiando esseri umani e non oggetti”, o la tesi per cui “la ricerca qualitativa é come la scrittura creativa: bisogna che tu sia un buon scrittore, quasi un poeta per poter trasmettere l’esperienza umana, non uno scienziato”. -published in Encyclopaideia: Rivista di Fenomenologia Pedagogia Formazione
photo credit: Philippe Moreau Chevrolet via photo pin cc